Paper for the NZAE Conference, 28-30 June 2006
Revisiting Some Economic Fundamentals
Stuart Birks, Massey University
 
Abstract
 
There are some basic aspects of economic theory which have developed over the past 200 or so years and now form the basis of much of our thinking as economists. Economic thinking has also had an impact on how society as a whole perceives itself. This paper explores some of the basic concepts, asking whether they are as generally applicable as might be assumed. It speculates on some possible alternatives, considering the implications that might arise from other paradigms.
 
  1. Introduction
 
Since I started down this line of investigation, I have been surprised how potentially fruitful it can be. It involves three steps. First, consider what are currently, commonly accepted starting assumptions upon which much later analysis has been built. Second, ask what alternative assumptions there might be that could have been used in their place. Third, speculate on whether these alternative assumptions might fundamentally alter our analyses and our conclusions. [1]
 
  1. Motivation
 
I was motivated to take this path by several references to academic disciplines relying more on faith in their foundations than being generally open to challenge (Birks, 2006c) . Joan Robinson provided an economic example in a paper (Robinson, 1970) in which she said the following:
 
Professor Ferguson, in The Neoclassical Theory of Production and Distribution, asserts that belief in neo-classical theory is a matter of faith. ‘I personally have the faith’, he declares… (p.309)
 
It is acceptable to build on an existing foundation if knowledge can be seen as a progression – so that where we are now is the cumulative effect of past knowledge and the foundations have been verified. However, if knowledge is a matter of perspectives, we might be off track, so it is worth looking at views from elsewhere, or other times, or, more generally, testing current perspectives.
 
As briefly indicated in the March 2006 issue of Asymmetric Information, one area I have been exploring in economics is that of utility (Birks, 2006a, 2006d) . Given the limited time available for this presentation, I shall limit myself to this area. I had intended to focus on two lines of enquiry. One, arising from passages written by David Hume, I have referred to as that of “stimulus and reflection”. The other, linked in to an increasing number of sources, is that of a “feeling of belonging” and a “sense of purpose”. The latter is significant as the considerations are central to major national and international policy initiatives, as observed in the focus on “inclusive” policies, the concept of relative deprivation, and broader definitions of health such as that adopted by the World Health Organisation. However, time precludes coverage here and it will have to be left for a subsequent paper.
 
  1. Stimulus and Reflection
 
2.1  Explanation
 
Consider what might be taken to be a general form for a utility function, U = f(X1,…Xn). When we use a function such as this, we are saying that utility in a given time period is a function solely of the quantities of (economic) goods and services consumed in that time period. Any other variables, such as family circumstances, health, or number of friends, are either associated characteristics of the goods and services, or are independently determined and can be ignored. With other standard economic assumptions, we are also claiming that the more we consume the higher our utility. When we use such a function to consider situations over time, we assume that the functional relationship at each time period is the same.
 
That is what we now take as a starting point in the theory of consumer behaviour, and it is used in numerous other areas, including welfare economics. It is perhaps surprising that we do this, given the far more circumspect origins of thought on utility. In that context, George Stigler (Stigler, 1950) points out, “most economists of the period [1776-1915] used utility theory primarily to explain economic behaviour (particularly demand behaviour) and only secondarily to amend or justify economic policy” (p.307). Thus it would be quite reasonable to focus on quantities of goods and services, as the problem being posed is to place values on these variables (as with determining quantities consumed by individuals). There is a major jump from this to the use of utility theory as a basis for determining desirable social policy.
 
Volume 1 of David Hume’s work, A Treatise of Human Nature, was published in 1748 (Hume, 1911) . While he was not writing directly on utility, he was writing at a time when he could have influenced the early deliberations about utility. In Part I Section II [2] he discusses what he calls impressions, and their role as the generators of ideas. He divides impressions into those of sensation and reflection (“reflexion”), describing the latter as passions, desires, and emotions. I appear to have subconsciously modified the original idea to refer to “stimulus and reflection”, which may be more meaningful today.
 
Briefly, Hume suggested that people experience something, and this gives an impression on the senses. This is then stored in the memory as an idea. Recollections of this memory serve as further experiences, even though they are just in the mind. This can go on through several iterations. We could imagine where we might have been if this had been incorporated into thinking about people’s utility. The act of consumption provides a stimulus, but this can then be followed by acts of reflection. [3] It could be considered that much of the pleasure gained arises through internal processing of experiences, in which case development of the ability to process effectively could be as significant for utility as the act of consumption itself.
 
Kahneman et al (Kahneman, Wakker, & Sarin, 1997) make a related distinction, referring back only to Bentham, when they talk of “Decision utility” and “Experienced utility”. [4] Experienced utility can be reported in real time (instant utility), or in retrospective evaluations of past episodes (remembered utility)” (p.375) They focus on discrepancies between the two forms of utility, resulting in suboptimal decisions arising from “systematic errors in the evaluation of past events and decisions that do not maximise future experienced utility” (p.376). There is a difficulty in terms of whether remembered utility has utility value, or is merely information that may be used in subsequent decisions. Kahneman et al focus on the suboptimal decision making that can result from using incorrect information, such that observed decision utility may reflect suboptimal decisions. Implicit in this approach is the assumption that the only real utility experienced is the instant utility, and remembered utility can result in decisions based on false information because of distorted recall and imperfect memory. The situation becomes more confused if people gain ongoing utility from recall or reflection, as I am suggesting here.
 
2.2  Implications
 
Had this perspective formed the basis of thinking on utility, economics would be very different today. We could speculate on this. It would mean that the utility of consumption is not dependent just on the characteristics of the goods and services consumed. It also depends on how individuals process the effects of consumption (reflection). In other words, both preferences and utility gained are endogenous, and we can become more efficient in generating utility.
 
2.2.1        Consumption having ongoing effects
According to Hume’s view, utility would not only be obtained directly from consumption. The act of consumption can produce multiple impressions as the act is recalled. The benefits of consumption are then as much a matter of how we retain and generate impressions as of the act of consumption itself. This could affect how we view economic activities. For example, we could think of holidays not as consumption, but as an investment in memories. As another example, might a child get more pleasure from one treasured toy, about which impressions can accumulate, than from many toys which are quickly forgotten? On another dimension, consider Mireille Guiliano’s book, French Women Don’t Get Fat: The Secret of Eating for Pleasure (Guiliano, 2005) , which emphasises savouring small quantities rather than consuming large quantities. Related to this, the sociology of food presents several wider aspects to food consumption (Beardsworth & Keil, 1997) . They suggest that preparing and eating food can be a social event, and “foodways can be seen as a kind of language encoding patterns of social relations, particularly those connected with social boundaries and with processes of inclusion and exclusion” (p.74). As such, they are an investment in social capital with longer-term implications. Similarly, despite the move to prepared foods and TV dinners, people may still experience the pleasure of waking up to the smell of bacon being fried, the anticipation caused by the cooking smells of a thick soup or beef casserole in winter, or an evening entertaining round the dinner table. Some of these things are to be savoured and recalled.
 
2.2.2        Endogenous preferences
A consideration of reflection has additional implications. Preferences and utility are unlikely to be fixed if they are based on a collection of sensations and reflections that is ever-increasing (or ever changing, at least, as people may forget). It would hardly be surprising, were we to develop and sustain distorted perceptions, but this may, to a degree, be unimportant. Some might argue that all perceptions are distorted, or at least shaped by their social context (Berger, 1967) . The act of reflection could be considered as an ongoing part of the process of consumption, in addition to being linked to experiences unrelated to consumption activities. Consequently change is ongoing, and internal thought processes can play an important part in determining utility. Some have even suggested that the focus should be on reflection, rather than stimulus, to the extent that satisfaction results as far as possible from the former alone. To quote Samuel Johnson [5] :
Without asserting Stoicism, it may be said, that it is our business to exempt ourselves as much as we can from the power of external things. There is but one solid basis of happiness; and that is, the reasonable hope of a happy futurity. This may be had every where.
 
2.2.3        Media, entertainment, information, knowledge and democracy
The media, for whatever purposes, provides information. It may be good or poor quality information. Numerous writers have distinguished between information and knowledge. [6] From an individual perspective, it could be argued that information requires reflection to be processed into knowledge. From this perspective, if today’s mass media are competing on circulation and audience ratings it would be legitimate to ask whether their actions result in too much stimulus and too little reflection. I recently presented one example of the possible distorting effects of this, whereby in news and other material there is a distorted presentation of issues in a way that is transient and superficial (Birks, 2006b) .
We could extend this aspect further, in that the stimulus of an experience via the media is detached from the lived reality. In other words, we could ask how realistic are these vicarious impressions? Even if the representations are factually accurate, audiences are detached observers, and they tend to see events from far more angles or perspectives, and get far more information in a more condensed form, than an individual in a lived experience. This has been recognised as a problem elsewhere in terms of the use of people’s preferences to determine social desirability of policy options, as discussed in (Birks, 2006e) . There is a complex relationship between experience and perception, and we rely on perceptions as a basis for expressed preferences in markets and democratic societies. This indicates a broadly based concern, namely –
 
2.2.4        Is there undue emphasis on stimulus activity at the expense of reflection?
Economists have accepted a focus on consumption of goods and services as a basis for wellbeing, along with the perspective that consumption has transient benefits. I have suggested above that this arises from a simplified focus on only part of the consumption process. In turn, this focus may have influenced the behaviour of and our attitudes to some of the institutions in society, the media being one example discussed here. It may be possible to increase wellbeing by i) reducing stimulus from economic goods and services and increasing stimulus from other activities, and ii) replacing some of the time spent on stimulus with time spent on reflection. This may also have implications for consideration of policy issues and the workings of democracy.
 
  1. Does it matter?
 
It could be asked, can’t we assume that people strike an optimal balance between stimulus and reflection, and stimulus from economic and non-economic goods and services? If so, then even though we as economists are taking a simplified approach, the distortions may not be as severe as otherwise (although there would still be implications of changing perceptions over time). There are reasons why we might consider the assumption of optimal balance to be unrealistic. To speculate, these could include; i) peer pressure; ii) government and other incentives emphasizing one over the other; and iii) society’s values arising from a utility framework (if we have successfully trained people to think like economists) that may understate reflection and associated aspects of lifestyle.
 
From an economic perspective, this raises a serious question. Does consideration of reflection highlight limitations in our analyses? I would suggest that it does. At the same time, section IX of This Simian World (Day, 1920) suggests that a lack of reflection might be an inherent characteristic of humans due to our simian origins:
 
By nature their itch is rather for knowing, than for understanding or thinking.  Some of them will learn to think, doubtless, and even to concentrate, but their eagerness to acquire those accomplishments will not be strong or insistent.  Creatures whose mainspring is curiosity will enjoy the accumulating of facts, far more than the pausing at times to reflect on those facts.  If they do not reflect on them, of course they'll be slow to find out about the ideas and relationships lying behind them; and they will be curious about those ideas; so you would suppose they'd reflect.  But deep thinking is painful.  It means they must channel the spready rivers of their attention.  That cannot be done without discipline and drills for the mind; and they will abhor doing that; their minds will work better when they are left free to run off at tangents.
 
 As one afterword, the additional considerations of “belonging” and “purpose”, mentioned above but not considered at length, are increasingly being emphasised in the wider policy environment even though they do not appear in utility functions. Consequently, economics risks becoming seriously out of step with major national and international policy initiatives. Discussion of these points will have to wait for another paper.
 
 
 
References
 
Beardsworth, A., & Keil, T. (1997). Sociology on the menu : an invitation to the study of food and society. London ; New York :: Routledge,.
Berger, P. L. (1967). The social construction of reality: a treatise in the sociology of knowledge. London,: Penguin P.,.
Birks, S. (2006a). David Hume, Impressions and Ideas. Asymmetric Information(25), 3.
Birks, S. (2006b, 27 May). Disgruntled Dads and the Family Court. Retrieved 31 May, 2006, from http://www.nzcpd.com/guest20.htm
Birks, S. (2006c). Economics as a discipline. Asymmetric Information(25), 8-9.
Birks, S. (2006d). Utility - a narrow concept? Asymmetric Information(25), 13-14.
Birks, S. (2006e). Whose preferences? Asymmetric Information(25), 14-15.
Boehm, C. (2004). What Makes Humans Economically Distinctive? A Three-Species Evolutionary Comparison and Historical Analysis. Journal of Bioeconomics, 6(2), 109-135.
Day, C. (1920). This Simian World. Retrieved 26 May, 2006, from http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/etext04/tsmnw10.txt
Guiliano, M. (2005). French Women Don't Get Fat: The Secret of Eating For Pleasure. London: Chatto & Windus.
Hume, D. (1911). A treatise of human nature, by David Hume .. London, New York,: J. M. Dent & sons, ltd.; E. P. Dutton & co.
Kahneman, D., Wakker, P. P., & Sarin, R. (1997). Back to Bentham? Explorations of Experienced Utility. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(2), 375-405.
Robinson, J. (1970). Capital Theory up to Date. The Canadian Journal of Economics, 3(2), 309-317.
Stenmark, D. (2002). The Relationship between Information and Knowledge and the Role of IT in Knowledge Management. Paper presented at the 35th Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences - 2002, Hawaii.
Stigler, G. J. (1950). The Development of Utility Theory. I. The Journal of Political Economy, 58(4), 307-327.
Wain, J. (Ed.). (1976). Johnson on Johnson. London: Dent.
 


[1] It might be expected that alternative perspectives could have a large effect on our perceptions and understanding, considering for example the much cited Berger and Luckmann’s The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge (Berger, 1967) . Clarence Day Jr took the back to basics approach even further in his publication, This Simian World (Day, 1920) . There he explores the possibility that our interests, motives and behaviour have been shaped by the instincts of our ape-like ancestors. He speculates on alternative societies, had some other creatures, such as cats or ants, evolved to dominate in our place, and takes an iconoclastic approach to human institutions and behaviour. On a more academic level, see the Journal of Bioeconomics, which links biology and economics, as with (Boehm, 2004) .
[3] Also as Professor Chatterjee suggested in a recent seminar, presumably thinking of certain Indian practices, the act of not consuming can also serve as a stimulus, often specifically intended to facilitate reflection.
[4] “‘Decision utility’ is the weight of an outcome in a decision. ‘Experienced utility’ is hedonic quality, as in Bentham’s usage.” (p.375)
[5] P.105 of (Wain, 1976)
[6] Several approaches are described in Table 1 of (Stenmark, 2002) .