Legal Reasoning and Economics
Stuart Birks
Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey
University
Paper for the NZAE Conference, Wellington, 12-14 July
2000
Abstract
Many
economic interventions involve the use of law. Lawyers and the
judiciary are guided by legislation, but have scope to interpret
that legislation. This paper looks at the reasoning that lawyers
and the courts consider acceptable, asking whether such
approaches are likely to lead to appropriate and consistent
decisions.
JEL:
K0
Stuart Birks
Director, Centre for Public Policy Evaluation
Massey University, Private Bag 11222
Palmerston
North
Phone:
06-350-5799 X2660
Fax:
06-350-5660
Email:
K.S.Birks@massey.ac.nz
1. Introduction
Lawyers have attracted much attention over the years. Coming from an economics background, I am inclined to view
this attention and the behaviour of lawyers in the context of patterns of reasoning. Much economic thinking, with all its
faults, is directed at methods of formulating and addressing issues to find the appropriate outcome or best decision. This
may therefore serve as a useful perspective to ask the question whether legal reasoning is such that it can be expected to
give "the appropriate outcome or best decision".
2. General Context
The first problem to overcome is that of specifying what might be meant by "legal reasoning". This is somewhat elusive,
but there are numerous clues. Some of these are discussed below.
2.1 Misinformation or activism
A 13th Century document suggests that, at that time, legal reasoning may have had its shortcomings:
Since these laws and customs are often misapplied by the unwise and unlearned who ascend the judgment seat before
they have learned the laws and stand amid doubts and the confusion of opinions, and frequently subverted by the
greater [judges] who decide cases according to their own will rather than by the authority of the laws, I,
Henry de Bracton, to instruct the lesser judges, if no one else, have turned my mind to the ancient judgments of just
men, examining diligently, not without working long into the night watches, their decisions, consilia and responsa, and
have collected whatever I found therein worthy of note into a summa, putting it in the form of titles and paragraphs,
without prejudice to any better system, by the aid of writing to be preserved to posterity forever.
[1]
Judges' ignorance of laws may not apply only in the distant past. It is not clear how, given s 20(a) of the Guardianship
Act 1968, otherwise to explain the statement in relation to obstructed enforcement of an access order that, "Judge Boshier
found that there was clear contempt, but doubted whether there was power to punish for such contempt" [2].
Are there also judges who "decide cases according to their own will rather than by the authority of
the laws"? In the third reading of the Protected Disclosures Bill on 29 March 2000,
Stephen Franks MP, said:
As a lawyer, I can tell members that there is more than ample obscurity in this bill. There is more than ample
confusion about what was really expected or intended for any judge to pare back the protection as he or she feels
fit. There is also more than ample opportunity for anyone who wants to misuse these procedures to take advantage
of them, and we could well find that we have the opposite of our intentions.[3]
To
some extent, it is through legal processes that the specific
nature of a law is determined. Cases are heard and decided,
decisions may be appealed, and over time a body of case law
develops which influences subsequent decisions. On this point,
Richardson made an interesting claim. "I think it helped to
have the same bench of judges hear all the early appeals [on the
Matrimonial Property Act]".[4] Can this
be likened to saying it is good to avoid political disagreements
by having a dictatorship?[5]
Elsewhere I have addressed the question of judicial activism in some detail with particular reference to a paper by
Judge Boshier.[6] The Judge has also been vocal specifically on this issue.[7]
To quote:
"Expect Judges to be much more vocal in the development of family law.
The former Chief Justice, Sir Thomas Eichelbaum, has signaled in successive reports on the New Zealand judiciary
that the public could expect Judges to be more visible in addressing issues of concern and participating in discussion
on some of those issues." (p.51)
"
I see nothing wrong with Judges commenting on bad laws and/or areas where administration of the law is failing
because of outdated statutes or failure on the part of the State to deliver as required by statute.
As long as there is a legislative presumption that Family Court cases may not be published, I think it inevitable and
desirable that Judges incline to be more active in bringing matters of concern to public attention." (p.52)
The former Chief Justice called for participation in discussion, a two way process. Judge Boshier's suggestion is
for a one way process.
A common criticism of judicial activism, where Judges
are proactive in the development of the law, is that Judges do
not have a mandate for this, nor are they accountable. It could
also be argued, that they are not appropriately informed either.
In particular, they are involved in and focus on individual cases,
thus taking a "micro" rather than a "macro"
perspective.[8] This is significant not only
because a large number of individual cases may have a wider
social impact, but also because individual cases can have an
impact on many situations which do not involve court appearances.
These situations involve operating "in the shadow of the law",
and can be influenced by possibility of legal intervention.[9]
While Judges and others prominent in law are more active
in promoting their own views, they have been reluctant to
participate in debate. Principal Family Court Judge Patrick
Mahony declined an offer to respond to a publication criticising
the Family Court on the grounds that, "It is not normal for
a Court to contribute to publications on policy issues".[10] However Teletext of 18
October 1999 reported, "Judge Patrick Mahony says in some
cases it may be fairer to give one person more than half of the
property or a portion of the future earnings of their
former partner." This was nothing new for him. He was
reported eight years earlier, in the Dominion Sunday Times
of 27 October 1991 (p.2), calling for women to get more that half
the assets in a marriage breakup. The same issue reported that,
"he would like the court's work to be put more before the
public" (p.11).
Similarly President of the Law Commission, Honourable
Justice Baragwanath, has not even responded to private and public
invitations to comment on published criticisms of the work of the
Law Commission.[11]
Reluctance to debate may be an engrained characteristic
of judges. To quote Hugo Young:
"The possibility that the system has erred is
the lifeblood of any barrister who finds himself in front of the
Court of Appeal. Yet when that barrister becomes a judge, the
same proposition inexplicably seems to tend towards one which he
feels obliged to repudiate unto his final breath."[12]
2.2 "Plausible stories", Persuasion or Proof?
Further insights into legal reasoning can be gleaned from quotes on lawyers. To quote Colin Brooks:
"It is on his skill in leading a jury to take
his view of fact and facts
that earns for a barrister the
reputation of being
good with juries."[13]
Brooks is suggesting that such a barrister chooses one
of possibly many interpretations of the facts. This is not a
general weighing up of information. Rather, a selection may be
made from the available information, this then being woven into a
"plausible story". Juries are then presented with
opposing stories, being faced with the choice of accepting one
and rejecting the other.[14]
Others have espoused the view that the law is a matter
of misinformation and trickery:
They have no lawyers among them [in Utopia] for they
consider them as the sort of people whose profession it is to
disguise matters." Thomas More, Utopia[15]
"There is no better way of exercising the
imagination than the study of law. No poet ever interpreted
nature as freely as a lawyer interprets the truth." Jean
Giradoux, Tiger at the Gates[16]
This would suggest that legal reasoning is such that
lawyers don't have to prove, they have to persuade.
Although the terms "beyond reasonable doubt", and
"balance of probabilities" are used, the doubts and
probabilities are subjective.
If so, it may be that parallels could be drawn with the
sophists of classical Greece:
"Protagoras was reputedly the first person to
write a treatise on techniques of argument, and was notorious for
his claim to make 'the weaker argument the stronger'."[17]
"[Sophists] emphasis upon worldly success as
well as their advocacy of the idea
that the ability to plead
a case and win depends on a skill that can be taught rather than
on having a just cause
were factors in promoting the
skepticism and moral relativism that were associated with their
name."[18]
Lawyers' techniques have also been described by the
Honourable Justice Robertson:
"The hallmark of most litigation was stealth
and surprise. You kept both
hands in your pocket, every rabbit still in the hat, and you
hoped, by avoiding any forewarning, to be able to steal a march
and win your client's case. That is not the law as I observe it
today... At least from the perspective of the outsider it is a
situation where the prime driving force frequently appears to be
a fees budget which has to be met to maintain a predetermined
standard of living and lifestyle."[19]
Contrary
to Justice Robertson's opinion, the suggestion of money as a
driving force is not new. Dickens observed that, "The
one great principle of the English law is to make business for
itself".[20]
2.3 Menu of Principles
Persuasion is a matter not only of "plausible
stories", but also of the criteria that are applied. These
influence the weight given to the various pieces of information.
It would be desirable to have consistent application of
principles, just as economic assessments would require consistent
values. Sometimes there may be several principles, in which case
there can be conflicts. With a lexicographic approach, the aim
would be to proceed as far as possible to meet the first
principle. If there are several options which are equally
successful in this aim, then selection would be made according to
their success with the second principle, and so on. It is more
likely that we would be concerned about trade-offs between
principles. How much simplicity would we be prepared to give up
to achieve more equity, for example? Economists might attempt to
weigh up competing objectives in this way. In law, however, we
are more likely to see judges drawing from a "menu of
principles". I have discussed this elsewhere[21], and there are further
examples in 3.1 and 4.2 below.
The "menu" concept means that there is no set
pattern for the application of principles. Rather, there are
several principles available and it is merely necessary for a
decision to be presented in such a way that it is clearly
consistent with the chosen principle or principles. It may well
be that the decision is inconsistent with other principles that
have not been mentioned. The decision making process then
involves not only the decision as presented, but also the choice
of principles. This latter may be neither transparent nor
explained. This introduces an element of uncertainty and scope
for arbitrary and inconsistent rulings.
2.4 Are Results "Process-dependent"?
"The art of cross-examination is not the art of
examining crossly. It's the art of leading the witness through a
line of propositions he agrees to until he's forced to agree to
the one fatal question." Clifford
Mortimer[22]
We see this process described by Robertson and Busch:
"
the questions we ask to a large extent
determine the outcomes we derive. It is one thing to ask, 'Did
you hit her?' but if the next question is 'Why did you hit her?'
the focus may immediately shift from the violence to the alleged
failings of the victim
To posit that there may be
circumstances in which violence is justified is to give the
abuser the right to define, control and mete out punishment in
respect of his partner's behaviour."[23]
Robertson and Busch object to the application, being
dissatisfied with the resultant outcome, but they do not
necessarily reject the method. It is a problem with any research
that the approach taken may determine the outcome. In law this
may be the deliberate intent. The lawyer's role is one of
advocate for one of the parties. The lawyer is paid to present
information so as to influence the outcome in the client's favour.
An alternative violence paradigm that Robertson and
Busch might prefer is that there is no excuse for male domestic
violence, that any violence or abuse shown by a male of the types
described in the Duluth Wheel is evidence of a patriarchal power
and control relationship, and that the male is then a "batterer"
and the female and any children in the family are "victims".[24]
This is not to deny the possible suitability of either
of these paradigms for some cases, but rather to illustrate that
a paradigm might be adopted as a result of a strategy by an
advocate for one side, rather than deliberate consideration and
the elimination of other possibilities.
There has been some recognition that terminology may be
important. Judge von Dadelszen has suggested that "parental
responsibility" be used in place of "custody" and
"access".[25]Similary
Judge Blaikie has suggested the use of the term "contact".
Hubin suggests that a more radical change might be needed to
shift current perceptions:
"The phrase "award of custody"
constitutes a strange twisting of reality in the context of
divorce, dissolution and most other conflicts over custody
between natural and adoptive parents. Such parents typically
appear before the court at the outset each with full parental
rights. Noone is awarded rights; one parent is deprived of rights."[26]
The representation of an issue can be crucial to people's
perceptions and to the outcome.
2.5 Expertise and Experts
Some would contend that similar behaviour in the form of
"advocacy research" is also adopted by some areas of
academia. This raises additional questions about the quality of
"expert" testimony:
"Over the last three decades ideological
doctrines have infiltrated the curricula of many of the larger
universities. Spurious academic subjects such as 'black
studies' and more recently 'women's studies', putatively designed
to 'raise consciousness' and strengthen commitment to credos of 'emancipation',
manifestly fail to meet the stringent requirements of scholarship:
certainly the doctrines of these ideologically inspired 'studies'
are not regarded by their proponents as provisional and refutable
hypotheses. Clearly arrangements being made for their
systematic propagation in these circumstances do not comport well
with the idea of a university as a forum for open-minded enquiry
and impartial scholarship."[27]
Given these problems and motivations, how much faith should we place in the ability of lawyers to understand, present
and weigh up information? Particular difficulties can arise if the information is outside the bounds of their legal training.
Socrates, describing good artisans, said, because they were good workmen they thought that they also knew all sorts
of high matters, and this defect in them overshadowed their wisdom[28]
Lawyers are trained in the law, but not in the specific
issues to which the law is applied. Hence they are not experts on
economics, or family relations, or medicine or the environment.
This is illustrated in answers to Questions for Written Answer
Nos. 10024 and 10025, lodged in the House on 30 May 2000:
"10024. Dr MURIEL NEWMAN to the
Minister of Revenue: What training is given to child
support review officers to enable them to critically assess
claimed income and expenditure levels?
Hon Dr MICHAEL CULLEN (Minister of
Revenue) replied: The Commissioner for Inland Revenue has
informed me that review officers do not receive specialized
training to enable them to critically assess claimed income and
expenditure levels.
If a review officer is unsure of any income or
expenditure details, then experienced staff (including
accountants) are made available to work through the issues with
them and enable them to make reasoned and appropriate decisions.
10025. Dr MURIEL NEWMAN to the Minister of Revenue:
Are child support review officers required to be familiar with
benefit entitlements, such as family assistance?
Hon Dr MICHAEL CULLEN (Minister of
Revenue) replied: The Commissioner for Inland Revenue has
informed me that it is not a requirement for child support review
officers to be familiar with benefit entitlements as these type
of enquiries would be redirected to the Department of Work and
Income.
Child Support officers, as staff of Inland Revenue,
will have knowledge on the concepts of benefits administered by
Inland Revenue such as Family Assistance and Parental Tax Credit."
Hence child support review officers, most of whom have a
law degree, do not have training so as to assess the accuracy of
parties' claims of income and expenditure and the resultant
circumstances under which they are living. Reviews are based on
the evidence presented. If review officers do not have the
appropriate background knowledge, they will not know what
information to challenge. Even if they do question some of the
information, they are unlikely to get informed advice while with
the parties and will not be able to challenge the information
later.
There are serious questions to raise about the way in
which "expert" information might be included in legal
deliberations, and how contrary expert opinions may be handled.
To rely on someone trained only in law to resolve such matters
could be likened to someone with no knowledge of French being
used to select the winner of a French oratory contest.
Hence the legal mind is not informed on the wider issues,
and legal reasoning appears not designed to give balanced
evaluation of the information, rather it is one of selective use
of information to present a story, and selective use of criteria
to support the client's interests.
3. Examples of Legal
Thinking
Mention has already been made of judges who are unhappy
with current laws. This dissatisfaction is likely to influence
their decisions where they have some discretion. This can occur
without public debate, and possibly even without public awareness.
Occasionally we do get a more public glimpse into the workings of
legal minds. Here are some examples.
3.1 Honourable Justice Baragwanath on affirmative
action
David Baragwanath, President of the Law Commission, was
interviewed by Brian Edwards in early 1998[29], said the following about the
appointment of women to academic positions:
DB - "... the consequences of it include, the
messages sent out, let's say to the potential women students that
may go to that faculty if this woman is appointed, and they
choose not to if she isn't. It's oversimple to say that the man
has a right to the job. He has not."
BE - "Well, you and I are going to have to
disagree on that. You've got to ask yourself how you're going to
feel. So I swan in there with a first class honours degree in
political science and there's a woman who's come in with a third
class honours degree in political science and she gets the job
purely because she's a woman."
DB - " Oh no. In that case of course you would
appoint the man. I am referring to two people who are of equal
potential, and if they are of equal potential, even though the
male is a distinguished person of your age and the female is a
youngster, if she's got it, if she has the capacity to perform
equally to him, she may well have the capacity to perform better,
you build that in. But ultimately it's to be remembered whose
interests you are looking at. It is not his interests, it's not
hers, it's the interests of the students and of the wider
community whose taxes are paying for the appointment."
The approach involves the definition of an unmeasured
variable ("potential"), which then allows someone to
attach a desired value to it. In this instance it allows measured
differences to be disregarded. The added assumption that women
academics are needed to attract women students then supports
preferential treatment over and above that afforded by the use of
the newly defined criterion. This can support any decision, even
if based on prejudice. In fact there have been more female than
male tertiary students since 1986. To illustrate a possible
weakness in the reasoning, let's follow the same theme further.
If the objective is to increase the number of women
academics, criteria could be selected from a "menu of
principles" to support this position in a range of scenarios.
Consider the following possibilities:
1) there are few women
students - more women academics are needed to encourage women
into the area.
2) there are about the
same number of women and men students - for balance, there should
therefore be about the same number of women and men academics.
3) Women students are in
the majority - it is a woman-focused area and students would be
uncomfortable with men academics, so most of the academics should
be women.
In other words, this approach is not a reasoned and
comprehensive assessment of the situation. It can be used to
apparently support a whole range of positions and cannot be
considered as sufficient on its own. In terms of decision making
or policy advice, it is seriously deficient.
The approach involves reliance on a criterion, plus
assumptions or information to support a conclusion based on that
criterion. The choice of criterion, including the decision to
reject other possible criteria, is not explained. There is no
consideration of a simultaneous consideration and weighing up of
several criteria. There may be problems with the relevance of
underlying assumptions or accuracy of information used.
The approach can result in over-simplification of issues
and inconsistency in approaches. If women are less than
proportionately represented in one area, they must be more than
proportionately represented in another. They are interconnected.
If representation in one is defined as a problem, then so also is
representation in the other. A solution could be directed at one,
or the other, or both, but one cannot be changed without changing
the other.
From an academic point of view, a requirement that might
be specified for appropriate policy advice is that a range of
alternatives be considered on the basis of consistently selected
and justified criteria, with suitable weighing up of conflicting
objectives and accurate underlying information. It should also be
open to critical evaluation and peer review.
If such reasoning is displayed in public, what is
happening behind close doors? It is to be hoped that it is not
representative of approaches where legal minds are expected to
consider factors other than simple points of law.
3.2 Annis Sommerville on superannuation
Annis Sommerville is
a Dunedin barrister and solicitor. In 1998 she became chairperson
of the Family Law Section of the New Zealand Law Society. The following is an extract from her paper at the 1995
New Zealand Law Society Family Law Conference. She compares the
option of realising an interest in an ex-husband's superannuation
in an immediate lump sum payment against an agreement whereby she
would get a share of payments when they are made to the husband:
"Superannuation
If the earner has
a superannuation fund, then the wife should consider negotiating
payment in a lump sum at the time of settlement rather than a [Matrimonial
Property Act 1976] s.31 agreement. Agreements persuant to s.31
have to be worded carefully if the wife is to be protected. The
Deed should bind the husband to be paid out by way of a lump sum
rather than by pension. If the husband has elected to be paid out
of his Fund by pension when he retires, the wife should ensure
that she is entitled in her own name to that pension. Her Legal
adviser should ensure that her entitlement is not contingent on
her husbands survival or a spousal benefit (which is not
applicable once she is divorced). If the husband dies soon after
retirement and she does not have any right in her own name, she
will miss out. Settlement agreements often trade off the husbands
share or part share in the house for his retaining the
Superannuation Fund. The woman keeping the house ends up without
a retirement fund but she has to weigh up the reality of a house
or a retirement fund. There are not a lot of choices when she is
the custodial parent."[30]
If Superannuation is correctly valued, there should be
no difference between its value as a lump sum and its value as a
possible future income stream. Nevertheless, Sommerville voices a
preference for a lump sum payout at the time of settlement. This
indicates that she considers the valuation for lump sum payment
to overstate the true value of the superannuation. She then
concludes by suggesting the woman loses out by not having a
retirement fund later. She seems unwilling to accept that there
are advantages and disadvantages to either option. She ignores
the equity from the lump sum payout as a basis for a retirement
fund, and she even suggests that s.31 splits should be taken as a
lump sum payments rather than as ongoing payments.
There are other aspects about which she appears ill-informed.
She shows ignorance of the Government Superannuation
Fund. The Fund only allows for a portion of the entitlement to be
taken in lump sum on retirement, and it does not allow
entitlements to be put into someone elses name such that
payments are not contingent on the contributing partys
survival.
If the husband dies soon after retirement, she is not
the only one to lose out. He will also lose out. If she gets a
lump sum on settlement and dies before he retires, then she is
getting more than she would have had they stayed married.
The valuation of superannuation for matrimonial property
settlement purposes should take account of the benefit of lump
sum payouts giving cash in hand at the time of settlement to the
non-contributing party. The contributor cannot obtain the funds
before retirement without bearing a possibly substantial penalty.
S.31 involves a sharing of the uncertainty about the
final sum paid out. Valuations for lump sum payments at
settlement should be lower because they are offering a certain
sum in exchange for an uncertain income stream. It is wrong then
for Sommerville to suggest that s.31 penalises the woman because
of such uncertainty.
If any contributions are made during a marriage, the
Matrimonial Property Act considers superannuation entitlements as
a result of contributions before marriage also to be matrimonial
property, although they are clearly not a result of the marriage
partnership.
If there is means-tested state superannuation, then the
income from a contributory scheme may reduce the superannuation
an individual receives from the state. This would arise even if
the recipient has made a lump sum payment to an ex-spouse based
on receipt of that superannuation. The recipient of a lump sum
payment would face no such reduction in entitlement as a result
of the lump sum received. The contributing party is therefore
disadvantaged
Superannuation received by someone who chooses to reside
overseas may be subject to tax in the country of residence, but
superannuation is valued on the basis of tax-free payments. The
superannuitant therefore faces a significant restriction that
does not apply to the recipient of a lump-sum payout on
separation, especially as the tax would be payable on all
superannuation, including that portion in exchange for which the
spouse received a lump sum payment.
4. Equity and Law - Two
Applications[31]
4.1 Equity
Outcomes
are more likely to be acceptable if they are considered equitable.
The Child Support Act 1991 refers to equity, and the Matrimonial
Property Act 1976 refers to "just division". What might
this mean?
Economists
refer to horizontal and vertical equity. Horizontal equity
relates to like circumstances, under which equitable outcomes
require like treatment. Vertical equity refers to differing
circumstances, for which an "appropriate difference" in
treatment is required.
"Like
circumstances" depend on the degree of detail considered -
should one look at current income, or lifetime income, or how the
income is earned, should one also consider the number of
dependants, their ages and specific needs? If there are problems
with the concept of horizontal equity, there are even greater
problems with vertical equity. "Appropriate differences"
in treatment depend on the variables used and the values placed
on them. Should time with children be considered? How should it
be measured - hours, days, nights? What costs should be included?
What effect would specific differences have on treatment?
Discussion
of disadvantage and discrimination hinge on the same points -
what variables are selected to draw comparisons, what are "appropriate
differences" and what values are assigned in terms of
specifying the significance of a difference and whether it is
considered beneficial or detrimental to a particular group.
Policy debate frequently revolves around differences in choice of
and interpretation of variables. For example, current proposals
for unequal splitting of matrimonial property are based on the
monocular consideration of caregivers' assumed sacrifice of
earning capacity, disregarding numerous other dimensions.
Resulting policy, often specified in legislation, can be confused
and inappropriate.
4.2 Child Support
Section
4 of the Child Support Act 1991 lists its objects. It is stated
on the IRD Child Support web page that: "Child Support is
governed by the objectives set out in the Child Support Act 1991".[32]
Child
support is paid by a liable parent to a custodial parent. Both
parties are assessed in a shared parenting situation, with a net
payment going from one to the other. I shall only consider the
formula under sole custody. Key aspects of the basic child
support formula in a sole custody situation are as follows:
· Child
support income is equal to taxable income up to a maximum level,
now $68,436.00.
· A living
allowance is deducted from this as follows:
Description |
Living Allowance |
Single with no dependent children |
$11,446.00 |
Married or defacto with no dependent children |
$15,501.00 |
Single, married or defacto with one child living
with the paying parent |
$20,001.00 |
Single, married or defacto with two children
living with the paying parent |
$24,445.00 |
Single, married or defacto with three children
living with the paying parent |
$26,889.00 |
Single, married or defacto with four or more
children living with the paying parent |
$29,333.00 |
Child
support is equal to the balance times a percentage rate, 18
percent for one child, 24 for two, 27 for three and 30 for four
or more children.
· The
custodial parent's income is not considered.
· The liable
parent's time with the children is not considered unless it
includes at least 40% of nights.
· There is
some scope to deviate from the formula through an administrative
review or hearing, but most applications by liable parents are
declined.
· If a
custodial parent is on the DBP, child support payments go first
to offset that payment. Any additional child support is passed on
to the custodial parent.
When
the objects of the Act are compared with the formula, several
inconsistencies can be observed. Neither the custodial parent's
income nor the liable parent's time with the children are taken
into account. Vertical equity cannot generally be achieved. If
the formula assessment is correct for one level of custodial
parent's income, then it is incorrect for others, and similarly
for time with children. There are also problems with payments not
being linked to expenditure on children, and with both parents
potentially being caregivers for some of the time. To consider
specific objects in the Act:
· Object
(a) is To affirm the right of children to be maintained by
their parents, but the act does not ensure that payments are
made by both parents, nor does it ensure that payments actually
benefit the child(ren).
· Object
(b) is To affirm the obligation of parents to maintain their
children, but the act focuses only on "liable parents".
· Object
(c) is To affirm the right of caregivers of children to
receive financial support in respect of those children from non-custodial
parents of the children, but non-custodial parents could be
the caregivers for up to 40 percent of nights with no effect on
child support obligations.
· Object
(d) is To provide that the level of financial support to be
provided by parents for their children is to be determined
according to their capacity to provide financial support, but
only liable parents are required to provide, and the other parent's
circumstances are generally not considered.
· Object
(e) is To ensure that parents with a like capacity to provide
financial support for their children should provide like amounts
of financial support, but under the formula this only applies
for comparisons between liable parents. The other parents'
circumstances are generally ignored.
· Similarly,
object (f), To provide legislatively fixed standards in
accordance with which the level of financial support to be
provided by parents for their children should be determined,
refers to parents, but the formula only refers to payments by
liable parents of money received by the state or by custodial
parents.
· Object
(h) is To ensure that equity exists between custodial and non-custodial
parents, in respect of the costs of supporting children, and
is commonly not met because only the circumstances of the liable
parent are considered.
· Object
(j) is To ensure that the costs to the State of providing an
adequate level of financial support for children and their
custodians are offset by the collection of a fair contribution
from non-custodial parents, but can it be a "fair"
contribution when there is no change in contribution as the
liable parent's time with the children rises from 0 percent to 40
percent of nights?
In
other words, the specifics of the law are inconsistent with its
objectives.
The
law commenced on 18 December 1991. There has since been a review
headed by Judge Peter Trapski.[33] Not only was there no mention of these inconsistencies,
but the Act also appears designed to achieve other unspecified
labour market objectives. On consideration of the custodial
parent's income the Consultative Document states: "a
strong disincentive to workforce participation could result if
every dollar earned by the custodian over a given threshold
resulted in a decrease in child support. As 84% of lone parents
are women, structural gender based inequities in the labour
market could be worsened." (p.24)
The
use of nights as a measure is also problematic. It is explained
in Butterworths Family Law in New Zealand as follows:
The
choice of 40 per cent of nights might at first appear curious but
it is probably explained by the fact that most children spend a
great part of the day time in school and most of the parental
care is later in the day and in the early morning with sleep in
between. [34]
Young
children are not at school, but for those who are there can be a
big difference between custodial and non-custodial parents
time with them. Non-custodial parents would generally care for
children at weekends and school holidays, when contact time and
associated expenses can be much greater.
It
could be suggested that anomalies can be allowed for through the
review process. However review officers are lawyers and may be
equally unaware of the problems. In fact some aspects, such as
the costs of enjoyment of access for the liable
parent, are expressly ignored. S 105(2)(b)(i) of the Act refers
specifically to the costs of "enabling access" only.
Rather
than ignorance, disregard for the inconsistencies may be tacitly
accepted because the status quo is considered desirable. Benson
describes how, in Commissioner of Inland Revenue v Aspinall
[1999] 3 NZLR 87, certain objects were considered and others
ignored.[35] Benson
is concerned about the decision in the case. In fact he
highlights a more serious problem, namely the judiciary's
adoption of a flawed line of reasoning. I refer in section 2.3
above to judges selecting, as convenient, from a menu of
principles to support of their preferred outcome. Benson
describes this process also. The result is a post hoc
rationalization for what may simply be the whim of the judge in
question. Judge Boshier has actively encouraged lawyers to "push
these boundaries".[36] This
covert form of judicial activism can be very harmful given the
judiciarys limited information and understanding of the
wider social implications of their actions. We see this in
operation elsewhere in family law.
According
to its title, the Matrimonial Property Act 1976 is: to
recognise the equal contribution of husband and wife to the
marriage partnership; to provide for a just division of the
matrimonial property between the spouses when their marriage ends
by separation or divorce.
There are two key aspects to this, equal contribution, and just division. There is a rebuttable presumption of equal
contribution. The decision as to whether contributions were equal or unequal would depend on the aspects considered
(choice of variables), and the values assigned to each of these components. Hence, under the presumption, a greater
paid work contribution by one party is considered to be balanced by a greater unpaid work contribution by the other.
This places an implicit value on unpaid work which can be determined by the explicit value of income earned from paid
work or other financial contributions. The difference in financial contribution is considered equal in value to the difference
in unpaid work contribution. Taken as a firm rule, this can lead to ludicrous valuations.[37]
Some of the sections of the legislation, such as those relating to the matrimonial home and chattels and to
superannuation, can serve to give extreme results. Unfortunately the Court is in a poor position to assess an
alternative value.
Another weakness in legal thinking is apparent where possibly tortuous reasoning may give inappropriate
results. Consider, for example, Lewis v Lewis [1993] 1 NZLR 569, which relates to the Matrimonial Property Act.
Section 8(c) states that all jointly owned property is matrimonial property. Section 10 states that property
acquired by succession or by survivorship or as a beneficiary under a trust or by a gift is separate property
except under specific circumstances such as via intermingling or by use for a matrimonial home. There is therefore
a conflict when the conditions for both sections are met. Which should be considered dominant? P.574 L54 to
P.545 L2 of Lewis v Lewis read:
It can be said that if Parliament had intended s 8(c) also to yield to s 10, a subordinating subject to
would have been provided. Since Parliament did not do this there is no sufficient reason for the Court to
read in such a qualification.
The decision is based on the presumed intent of Parliament. Pp.4108-4111 of Hansard of 23 November
1976 (Vol.408) contains Mr McLays speech presenting the report of the committee on the Matrimonial Property
Bill. On p.4109 he defines matrimonial property, including the terms of section 10 without qualification by
section 8(c). He is even clearer introducing the second reading in his speech of 9 December 1976 (pp.4721-4722):
The other suggestion made, which is, in my opinion, an irresponsible suggestion, is that the Bill is some
way represents a confiscation of property The purpose of the legislation, in my view, is to enable possession
to be given, or a just and proper apportionment to be made, of those capital family assets which Lord Denning
has referred to as the things intended to be a continuing provision for the parties during their joint lives, the
working capital of the marriage partnership that may be generically described and I underline the words
marriage partnership, in contrast, for example, with formal gifts or investments brought to the marriage by
one party or the other, or achieved by incomes ranging well outside the normal family needs.
As if that was not clear enough, he then reiterated the significance of the term marriage partnership. The closing
comment in the quote may also be of interest for those following Z v Z [1997] NZFLR 241.
The concepts of horizontal and vertical equity are useful for identifying the real interpretation of equal contribution
under the Act. Consider two couples, identical except that in one couple someone entered with ten years of prior
superannuation contributions. The presumption of "equal contributions" would mean that all the other contributions
made by that person are found to be worth less by the value of the prior superannuation. How can this be justified?
To add another dimension, should the consideration of this be different if that person had already made a lump sum
payment to a previous spouse because of that superannuation?
As another example, consider someone who received an inheritance. If it is kept separate, there is no change
to the perceived value of contributions to the marriage partnership. If it is put into the family home, then the other
contributions by that person are considered to be worth less by the amount of the inheritance. And for another
dimension, if one person's inheritance is included in matrimonial property, should consideration be made of an
anticipated inheritance by the ex-partner?
For yet another example, someone could consider marrying one of two people, then contributing by keeping
house. The tasks performed in either marriage would be identical, but one potential partner has an annual income
of $100,000, the other $25,000. If the partner does nothing besides earn, then keeping house is valued at four times
more in one marriage than in the other.
Paradoxically, while the Matrimonial Property Act considers unpaid work in the home to be a significant and
valued contribution, the Child Support Act does not. Equal sharing under the Matrimonial Property Act implies
an intra-family sharing of income, but a homemaker who is a liable parent under the Child Support Act would be
assessed as having no income, and an income earning liable parent will receive minimal consideration for the
presence of a homemaker partner.
We could ask why marriage has a special significance, especially given proposals to apply the legislation to
other relationships. A just division is called for if a marriage lasts for three years or more. Someones grown-up
child could live in the same home for three years and have no claims on the family assets when leaving, but an adult
can enter the family for the same time and leave with a claim on half the assets. While the Act's title refers to taking
account of the interests of any children of the marriage, it makes no reference to other children from a previous marriage.
Under the legislation, assets are transferred rapidly from one adult to another when one brings more wealth
or earning power to the relationship than the other. The more someone brings to a relationship in terms of assets
and earning power, the lower the Court values him/her as a person. What will the long-term social implications be
in terms of peoples willingness to earn and save, to plan for the future, to acknowledge the contribution of others,
and even to form stable relationships?
It is in this context that lawyers and the judiciary are intervening in peoples lives and applying policies in
their own way, possibly quite at odds with the original intention of the policymakers. They do this with limited
supervision and accountability and with a marked reluctance to publicly debate and justify their actions.
5. Conclusion
Viewed from an economics perspective on the requirements for determining an optimal solution to a problem, legal reasoning appears to have several weaknesses. It may be that, in an ideal legal system, laws are correctly specified, lawyers then apply the laws as intended, and there is appropriate expert input in areas where the lawyers' expertise is inadequate. In practice it appears that lawyers are operating in areas where they are poorly informed, they do not always know when they need outside expert assistance, and they are working with laws that have shortcomings, in an atmosphere whereby the judiciary may be keen to modify laws at their own pace without external supervision. In addition, the approach taken in advocating for a client may affect the style and content of information presented.
Research funding is required to investigate these
matters further.
[1] Bracton on the Laws and Customs of England (attributed to Henry of Bratton, c. 1210-1268) http://bracton.law.cornell.edu/bracton/Common/index.html, this extract is at: http://supct.law.cornell.edu/bracton/Unframed/English/v2/19.htm
[2] Butterworths (1995) Butterworths Family Law in New Zealand, 7th edition, Wellington: Butterworths. S 20(a) of the Guardianship Act specifies penalties for hindering or obstructing access. See section 6.3 of Birks S (1998) Gender Analysis and the Women's Access to Justice Project, Issues Paper Number 2, Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey University http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/waj1.htm)
[3] http://rangi.knowledge-basket.co.nz/hansard/han/text/2000/03/29_045.html.
[4] Para.2.11 of Richardson I L M (1999) "Family Courts: Some Questions for Consideration", Australasian Family Courts Conference, 16 October 1999
[5] Something similar was lampooned in The Mikado: "KoKo:
so I consulted the Attorney-General, the Lord
Chief Justice, the Master of the Rolls, the Judge Ordinary, and the Lord Chancellor. They're all of the
same opinion. Never knew such unanimity on a point of law in my life." (From Act 2 of The Mikado, by W.S.Gilbert.
All these posts were filled by one person, Pooh-Bah.)
[6] See sections 2.8-2.10 of Birks (1998) The Family Court: A View from the Outside, Issues Paper No.3¸ Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey University
(http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/cppeip03.htm), discussing Boshier P (1998) "Developments in Matrimonial Property", Family Law Conference, 31st August 2nd September 1998, Christchurch, New Zealand Law Society, pp.51-69.
[7] Boshier P F (1999) "Editorial: Judicial activism and law reform", Butterworths Family Law Journal, September, pp.51-52
[8] See section 2.10 of Birks (1998) The Family Court: A View from the Outside, Issues Paper No.3¸ Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey University, http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/cppeip03.htm
[9] http://www.massey.ac.nz/~KBirks/gender/econ/shadow.htm, and section 3 of Birks S "Parenting and the
Family Court: An Economist's Perspective", in Birks S and
Callister P (eds.) (1999) Perspectives on Fathering II, Issues
Paper No.6¸ Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey
University.
(http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/cppeip06/cppeip06.htm)
[10] Personal correspondence, 30th September 1999.
[11] See, for example, the letter in the New Zealand law Journal, December 1999, p.437.
[12] Pp.164-165 of Young H, "Judges' convictions", in Course J (ed.) (1991) The Bedside Guardian 1991, London: Fourth Estate Books, pp.164-169, reprinted from The Guardian, 12 July 1990.
[13] (Brooks, 1952, pp.74-75) Brooks C (1952) More Tavern Talk, London: James Barrie
[14] For more on "plausible stories", see section 4.2 of Birks S (1998) Gender Analysis and the Women's Access to Justice Project, Issues Paper Number 2, Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey University http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/waj1.htm)
[15] Rawson H and Miner M (1986) The New International Dictionary of Quotations, New York: Dutton, p.145, and http://www.d-holliday.com/tmore/utopia008.htm
[16] Ibid p.144
[17] Hornblower S and Spawforth A (eds.) (1996) The Oxford Classical Dictionary, 3rd edition, Oxford, OUP, p.1422.
[18] Howatson M C (ed.) (1997) The Oxford Companion to Classical Literature, 2nd edition, Oxford, OUP, p.531.
[19] Robertson, Hon. Justice (1999) "The 'Lost Lawyer' - Where Have She and He Gone?" paper to the New Zealand Law Conference, 1999
[20] http://www.fidnet.com/~dap1955/dickens/works.html
[21] See Section 4.2 of Birks S (1998)
Gender Analysis and the Women's Access to Justice Project,
Issues Paper Number 2, Centre for Public Policy Evaluation,
Massey University (http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/waj1.htm); section 2.8 of Birks S (1998) The Family Court: A
View from the Outside, Issues Paper No.3¸ Centre for Public
Policy Evaluation, Massey University (http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/cppeip03.htm); section 3.4 of Birks S "Parenting and the Family
Court: An Economist's Perspective", in Birks S and Callister
P (eds.) (1999) Perspectives on Fathering II, Issues Paper No.6¸
Centre for Public Policy Evaluation, Massey University.
(http://econ.massey.ac.nz/cppe/papers/cppeip06/cppeip06.htm)
[22] From John Mortimer (1982) Clinging to the wreckage (quoted in Sherrin N (1995) The Oxford Dictionary of Humorous Quotations, Oxford: OUP, p.173)
[23] Robertson N and Busch R, "The Dynamics of Spousal Violence: Paradigms and Priorities", in Pipe M-E and Seymour F (eds.) (1998) Psychology and family Law: a New Zealand Perspective, Dunedin, University of Otago Press, p.55
[24] This paradigm would be familiar to many and is described at: http://www.justice.govt.nz/pubs/reports/1999/family_conference/author_20.html, and at: http://actag.canberra.edu.au/actag/Reports/CLRC/r9/dov7.html (now at: http://www.dpa.act.gov.au/ag/Reports/CLRC/r9/dov7.html [22 August 2000]).
[25] Dadelszen von P (1995) The case for change: parental responsibility not custody and access, Butterworths Family Law Journal, December, pp.263-268
[26] P.136 of Hubin D C (1999) "Parental rights and due process", Journal of Law and Family Studies, 1(1999) pp. 123-150. Also at: http://freeload.homestead.com/_ksi0701961573075034/pacecolumbus/files/prdp.pdf
[27] Mishan E.J. (1993) The Costs of Economic Growth, Revised Edition, Westport: Praeger, p.202
[28] Socrates Apology by Plato, from: Gibbons R (compiler) (1995) In Their Own Words, New York: Gramercy Books, p.10
[29] "Top of the Morning", on National Radio, possibly broadcast 10th January 1998.
[30] P.56 of Sommerville, A (1995) "Money, Money, Money The Economic Consequences for the Homemaker upon the Break Up of a Marriage in relation to Child Support, Spousal Maintenance and Matrimonial Property", Conference Session Papers, New Zealand Law Society Family Law Conference, Wellington 2-4 October 1995, pp.41-58
[31] A version of this section of the paper is forthcoming in the New Zealand Law Journal.
[32] http://www.ird.govt.nz/childsupport/csa.htm#legislation
[33] See Child Support Act Working Party (1994) Child Support Review 1994: A Consultative Document, and Trapski P, et al. (1994) Child Support Review 1994: Report of the Working Party, Wellington: Inland Revenue Department
[34] Butterworths (1995) Butterworths Family Law in New Zealand, 7th edition, p.294
[35] Benson S (2000) "Departures from Child
Support Assessments", New Zealand Law Journal, May,
pp.176-179
[36] Boshier P (1998) "Developments in
Matrimonial Property", Family Law Conference, 31st August
2nd September 1998, Christchurch,
New Zealand Law Society, pp.51-69.
[37] See Birks S (1994) Women, Families and Unpaid Work, School of Applied and International Economics, Massey University, Discussion Paper 9.49, October. A modified version is at: http://www.massey.ac.nz/~KBirks/gender/econ/unp4web.htm